Can Marginal Rates of Substitution Be Inferred From Happiness Data? Evidence from Residency Choices

My second paper coauthored with Dan Benjamin, Ori Heffetz and Alex Rees-Jones showing that happiness and utility are distinct is now available to everyone free on PubMed at the link above. 

The first is available at the link below:

What Do You Think Would Make You Happier? What Do You Think You Would Choose?

Aristotle's Eudaimonia

Aristotle saw people not as striving to maximize a state of satisfaction, and also not as striving to perform a list of duties. He saw them, instead, as striving to achieve a life that included all the activities to which, on reflection, they decided to attach intrinsic value.

Virginia Postrel on Ideals

Every culture, [Grant McCracken] observes, maintains ideals that can never be fully realized in everyday life, from Christian charity to economic equality. These ideals may uphold incompatible principles, deny the relation of cause and effect, require impossible knowledge, or demand more consistent or emotionally contradictory behavior than human beings can sustain. Yet for all their empirical failings, such cultural ideals supply essential purpose and meaning, offering identity and hope. To preserve and transmit them, cultures develop images and stories that portray a world in which their ideals are realized–a paradise, a utopia, a golden age, a promised land, a world to come (whether after death, the Messiah, the Second Coming, the Revolution, or the Singularity).

– Virginia Postrel, The Power of Glamour, p. 41

Virgina Postrel: Glamour Reveals Nonsatiation

Even in its most apparently superficial and entertaining forms, glamour reveals inner truths. It exposes our vulnerabilities, to ourselves and perhaps to the world. We feel lonely, frustrated, and unappreciated; we long for fellowship, for meaningful work, for true love. We are social and biological creatures. We want to be looked at and admired, to be rich and powerful, to be painlessly heroic and effortlessly beautiful. We long to be sexually desired and recognized as special. Glamour defies demands for humility or modesty, self-denial or patient resignation. It is ambitious and self-involved. Above all, glamour reveals that we want to be something we are not. It demonstrates that we are not wholly content with life as it is. Glamour is pleasurable, but it is also disquieting.

– Virgina Postrel, The Power of Glamour, p, 221

Virginia Postrel: The Illusion of Living Without Illusions

One job of intellectuals is to puncture glamour by reminding us of what’s hidden. But intellectuals are by no means exempt from glamour’s effects. They simply have their own longings and hence their own versions of glamour, including in some cases the ideal of a life without meaningful illusions.

– Virginia Postrel, The Power of Glamour, p. 221

Virginia Postrel: The Glamour of Harmony

… [the 1939 New York World’s Fair’s] merchandising sold both political planning and commercial products—and packaged both in glamour. It encouraged visitors to project themselves into a future not only of abundant goods and impressive technology but of effortless harmony and order. The fair did not acknowledge any contradiction between individual choices in the marketplace and ‘cooperative’ political planning. In its glamorous depictions of the future, all groups worked together in harmony, and individual and collective plans exactly coincided. By editing out conflicts, the fair heightened the allure of both its commercial exhibits and the politically directed future. It sold a world where everyone wanted the same thing, a world without trade-offs or losers.

– Virgina Postrel, The Power of Glamour, pp. 191-192

Virginia Postrel: The Glamour of Terrorism

Jihadi terrorism combines two ancient forms of glamour, the martial and the religious, with the modern allure of media celebrity. It promises to fulfill a host of desires: for purity and meaning, union with God, historical significance, attention and fame, a sense of belonging, even (posthumous) riches and beautiful women. The jihadi’s ultimate goal of a restored caliphate exemplifies the glamorous utopia, while the terrorist plot recalls the synchronization of heist movies, with a secret and intricate plan in which every team member is important and the goal is to outwit authorities and commit a crime. It’s not hard to imagine how appealing all this might be to a bored, alienated, and impressionable person.

– Virgina Postrel, The Power of Glamour, pp. 220-221

Virginia Postrel on Charisma

In its precise sense, charisma (originally a religious term) is a quality of leadership that inspires followers to join the charismatic leader in the disciplined pursuit of a greater cause. … Glamour doesn’t persuade the audience to share a leader’s vision. Instead it inspires the audience to project their own longings onto the leader … making glamour most effective at a distance. Charisma, by contrast, works through personal contact. … Charisma draws the audience to share the charismatic figure’s own commitments, seeking that person’s affection or approval. Charisma enhances leadership, glamour enhances sales.

– Virginia Postrel, The Power of Glamour, pp. 116-117

Virginia Postrel: Glamour and Yearning

This then is what glamour does as rhetoric. It focuses preexisting, largely unarticulated desires on a specific object, intensifying longing. It thus allows us to imaginatively inhabit the ideal and, as a result, to believe–at least for a moment–that we can achieve it in real life. … Glamour is defined not by the specific desires it promotes but by the process of projection and sense of yearning it creates and … by the recurring elements that generate that projection and yearning: the promise of escape and transformation; grace; and mystery.

– Virginia Postrel, The Power of Glamour, p. 41

Virginia Postrel: Jet Age Glamour

Jet Age glamour expressed the longing to experience a world of variety and excitement, a fast-moving, dynamic, and diverse alternative to the familiar and routine. We now inhabit the real version of that world, a world glamour advertised and helped bring about. We can never bring the old illusion back. We can only invent new ones, reflecting new circumstances, new possibilities, new desires, and new versions of yearnings that never go away.

– Virginia Postrel, The Power of Glamour, p, 199

Virginia Postrel: The Glamour of Autonomy and the Glamour of Synchronization

If autonomy represents the glamour of standing out, synchronization offers the glamour of fitting in. … Here actions, goals, and personalities mesh smoothly. Synchronization encompasses the social glamour of witty repartee–saying the right thing at the right moment, not an hour later–and of camaraderie in a common cause. It intensifies the glamour of fellowship, making the connections between people seem intuitive or telepathic. … Both autonomy and synchronization are illusions, of course, requiring drastic simplifications of reality. Autonomy suggests that we can shed the constraints of complex relationships, whether familial ties or electrical grids, without sacrificing their benefits. Synchronization omits the trials and rehearsal that real coordination requires. It hides conflict and disguises the compromises necessary to achieve apparent harmony. It assumes goals that are not only shared but worthy.

– Virginia Postrel, The Power of Glamour, pp. 94-95

Cognitive Economics

The image above is a computer simulation of the branching architecture of the dendrites of pyramidal neurons from the Wikipedia article on “Mind.”

The image above is a computer simulation of the branching architecture of the dendrites of pyramidal neurons from the Wikipedia article on “Mind.”

Here is a link to an ungated copy of my paper "Cognitive Economics" as it appears in the Japanese Economics Review. By special arrangement with the Japanese Economics Review, this paper is in the public domain. The presentation I gave at the Japanese Economic Review conference for this conference volume is here

This paper is written in the same style as my more academic blog posts. So I count it as a major blog post as well as an NBER Working Paper. It just happens to be a blog post that you need to follow a link to see in full. (And sadly, like the typical blog post, despite diligent efforts, a few typos have crept through. The number and severity of typos I find will have to reach a certain critical threshold before I put the NBER staff to the work of putting together a new version. Please let me know if you find a typo)  

Let me give you a bit of a preview, in the form of an outline with one or more key quotations from each section and subsection:

I. Introduction

  • … research in “Cognitive Economics” has already been underway for a long time. But as a participant in this subfield, it seems to me that research in this area has been growing in recent years.

II. Defining Cognitive Economics

  • Cognitive Economics is defined as the economics of what is in people’s minds. In practical terms, this means that cognitive economics is characterized by its use of a distinctive kind of data. This includes data on expectations, hypothetical choices, cognitive ability, and expressed attitudes.

  • The name “Cognitive Economics” might initially sound as if it might be yet another synonym for Behavioral Economics … The most obvious difference is that Cognitive Economics is narrower. Behavioral Economics addresses a huge range of issues and cuts across all of the data types listed above, while Cognitive Economics focuses primarily on innovative kinds of survey data … Second, important pieces of Cognitive Economics are inspired by the internal dynamic of economics rather than by psychology.

  • … there is an obvious complementarity between Cognitive Economics and Behavioral Economics. Although it is possible to consider nonstandard theories of human behavior on the basis of standard data on market decisions alone, freeing up economic theory from traditional assumptions tends to increase the number of free parameters. There is a great value to additional data that can help pin down these additional free parameters.

  • … let me give my opinion on existing research and future directions in Cognitive Economics, organized around three themes: using data on hypothetical choices and mental contents (1) to identify individual heterogeneity, (2) to revisit welfare economics and (3) to study finite cognition.

III. Identifying Individual Heterogeneity

  • Heterogeneity across individuals in preferences and cognitive ability is not at all controversial. But data limitations have often forced economists to assume uniformity. Here the kind of data discussed above can do a lot to allow economists to capture some of the heterogeneity that exists.

IV. Revisiting Welfare Economics

  • The use of self-reported happiness to study welfare issues illustrates a key methodological issue in Cognitive Economics. Whenever a new measure is used, its relationship to standard concepts of economic theory is at issue.

  • It is possible, however, that happiness data could have a tight relationship to preferences even if the level of happiness does not. In particular, to explain the data, Kimball and Willis (2006) suggest that a large component of self-reported happiness depends on recent innovations in lifetime utility. Whenever people receive good news about lifetime utility, self-reported happiness temporarily spikes up; whenever people receive bad news about lifetime utility, self-reported happiness temporarily dips down. If true, this means that while it is questionable to use the level of happiness to infer preferences, the dynamics of happiness are informative about preferences and so can be used to inform welfare economics.

V.  Studying Finite Cognition

  • Moreover, to avoid the judgment Herbert Simon’s phrase “bounded rationality” can inadvertently suggest, I will refer instead to “finite cognition.”[3] Finite cognition means something more than just imperfect information—it means finite intelligence, imperfect information processing, and decision-making that is costly.

  • [3] Often, the inadvertent judgment suggested by “bounded rationality” is quite inappropriate. For example, if decision-making is actually costly, which is more “rational,” to choose in a way that takes into account the costliness of decision-making or to pretend that decision-making has zero cost? If one’s intelligence is actually finite, which is more rational, taking into account the limits on one’s intelligence, or pretending that one’s thinking power is unlimited? There is certainly a sense in which knowing and adjusting to one’s own limitations can often be the height of “rationality.”

  • finite cognition implies that even in the absence of externalities, welfare can often be improved by economic education, setting up appropriate default choices for people, or providing disinterested, credible advice. By contrast, explanations of puzzling behavior on the basis of individuals maximizing exotic preferences imply (if true) that welfare improvements must come in the standard way from addressing externalities, or in the case of inconsistent preferences, by taking sides in an internal conflict. Once puzzling behavior that is difficult to explain on the basis of standard economic theory is identified, it is hard to think of a more important question than whether people behave that way because they want to, or simply because they are confused.

A. The Reality of Finite and Scarce Cognition.

  • Although the inadequacies of our current tools can make it hard to study finite cognition theoretically, the claim that human intelligence is finite–and that finite intelligence matters for economic life—scarce cognition—is not really controversial.[4]

  • [4] There are many problems that are too hard for even very high levels of intelligence. For example, one of the problems with Bayesian updating is that, strictly speaking, it involves putting a positive probability on a much greater than astronomically huge set of possibilities. Various strategies of economizing on information processing are always essential in practice. Even the existence of a utility function itself is, in a sense, a technique of economizing on information transfer and processing. If evolution could process an infinite amount of information, and the genetic code could transmit an infinite amount of information, we could be endowed with decision rules embracing essentially all contingencies instead of mere objective functions and calculation capabilities.

B. Difficulties in Studying Finite Cognition with Standard Theoretical Tools.  

  • One key reason it is not easy using our standard theoretical tools to model finite cognition is the “infinite regress” problem emphasized by John Conlisk (1996). The infinite regress problem afflicts models that assume a cost of computation or other decision-making cost. The problem is that figuring out how much time to spend in making a decision is almost always a strictly harder decision than the original decision.

  • Costs to decision-making are a natural enough assumption for economists that a substantial percentage of all applied economic theory papers might include them, if it were not for the infinite regress problem. Finessing the infinite regress problem somehow is essential if economists are to develop effective theoretical tools for studying finite cognition. There are several feasible strategies for getting around the infinite regress problem—every one of which requires breaking at least one inhibition shared by many economists.

  1. Least transgressive are models in which an agent sits down once in a long while to think very carefully about how carefully to think about decisions of a frequently encountered type.

  2. A second strategy is to give up on modeling finite cognition directly and use models of limited information transmission capacity as a way of getting agents to make more imperfect decisions. In other words, one can accept the fact that our standard tools require constrained optimization with its implication of infinite intelligence somewhere in the model, but handicap agents in the model by giving them a “thick skull” that is very inefficient at transmitting information to the infinitely intelligent decision-maker within (that is, the perfect constrained optimizer within).

  3. A third feasible strategy is in the spirit of what the complexity theorists call “agent-based modeling. … This type of modeling substitutes the problem of agents that have unrealistically subhuman intelligence for the problem we have been focusing on of agents that have unrealistically superhuman intelligence. Despite this lack of realism, the results can be very instructive because the failure of realism is in the opposite direction from what economists are used to.

  4. I would like to focus on a fourth strategy for getting around the infinite regress problem–one that seems to me less commonly used: modeling economic actors as doing constrained optimization in relation to a simpler economic model than the model treated as true in the analysis. This simpler economic modeled treated as true by the agent can be called a “folk theory.“ … A folk theory should not be confused with the Folk Theorem of repeated game theory. I am talking about folk economics in the same sense as the well established ideas of “folk psychology,” “folk physics” and “folk biology.”

C. Modeling Unawareness Requires a Subjective State Space for the Economic Actor Distinct from the True State Space.

  • Dekel, Lipman and Rustichini (1998) argue for relaxing what they call the “real states” assumption as follows:

  • In standard state-space models, states play two distinct roles: they are the analyst’s descriptions of ways the world might be and they are also the agent’s descriptions of ways the world might be. If the agent is unaware of some possibility, though, ‘his’ states should be less complete than the analyst’s. In particular, the propositions the agent is unaware of should not ‘appear in’ the states he perceives.

  • Departures from the real states assumption would allow agents to have a different model of the economic situation in their minds than the maintained assumptions the analyst is using to model the situation of those very agents.

  • Note that if someone is successfully taught a more sophisticated model, this would involve an expansion in the individual’s subjective state space. If positive probabilities were accorded to the newly added states, this must necessarily involve a departure from Bayesian updating. Presumably it is also possible for people to “see the light” even without being explicitly taught. For example, the agent might be driven to entertain an expanded model if the probability of observed events conditional on the initial folk model ever appeared sufficiently low. We all recognize the practical importance of expansions in one’s subjective state space when in scientific contexts we say “Asking the right question is half the battle.”

D. Using Folk Theories to Model Finite Cognition: A Portfolio Choice Example. 

  • Clearly, the desirable properties for a modeled folk theory are quite different from the desirable properties for a theory proposed as a good approximation of reality. A folk theory need not be logically consistent at a deep level. Indeed, in representing reality, it may be a positive virtue for a folk theory to have logical inconsistencies of a form similar to the logical inconsistencies real people might have in their views of the world. Other than (a) descriptive accuracy as a reasonable representation of how people actually view the world, for theoretical purposes the key desirable properties for a modeled folk theory are (b) providing a clear prediction for how the people holding that folk theory will behave in various circumstances and © representing clearly what the people holding the folk theory are confused about and what they do understand. In terms discussed in Richard Herrnstein (1997)–particular in the chapters with Drazen Prelec–a folk theory should at least implicitly model the accounting framework that an agent uses, in addition to the objective function. Because it need not be logically consistent at a deep level, the argument for a folk theory can involve (correct reasoning about) logical leaps and plausible, though fallacious reasoning.

  • In reality, I am confident that people’s thinking about portfolio choice varies from person to person with a wild profusion of different kinds of misunderstanding. In most other contexts as well—at least where there is some complexity–any model that assumes everyone’s folk theory is of the same type is likely to be false. Realizing that people don’t always have the same mental model of a situation as the economist studying that situation is the first step toward facing the motley truth about people’s folk theories.

VI. Conclusion

  • Economic research using more and more direct data about what is in people’s minds is flourishing. But much more can be done. Fostering continued progress in this area of Cognitive Economics calls for three inputs. First, new theoretical tools for dealing with finite cognition need to be developed, and existing theoretical tools sharpened. Second, welfare economics needs to be toughened up for the rugged landscape revealed by peering into people’s minds. Third, the statement “The data are endogenous” needs to become not only an econometrician’s warning but also a motto reminding economists that new surveys can be designed and new data of many kinds can be collected to answer pressing questions.

Virginia Postrel: The Glamour of Star Trek

Star Trek’s allure may be lost on fashionistas, but for the right audience, the show’s distant and idealized universe offers it own glamour, arising from the graceful, mysterious setting: a future where today’s conflicts and frustrations have disappeared. … Like studio-era movies, this fictional setting addresses not one but many different kinds of desire. It offers the obvious allure of adventure and exploration, along with Star Trek’s famously inclusive vision of “infinite diversity in infinite combinations.” But many fans cite another, less remarked-upon appeal, analogous to the glamorous portrayal of married affection in old movies: the idea of a highly functional, meritocratic workplace where ‘everyone has a role, and is important.’

– Virginia Postrel, The Power of Glamour, p. 40

Richard L. Evans: Every True Strength Is Gained in Struggle

You may search all the ages for a person who has had no problems, you may look through the streets of heaven asking each one how he came there, and you will look in vain everywhere for a man morally and spiritually strong whose strength did not come to him in struggle. Do not suppose that there is a person who has never wrestled with his own success and happiness. There is no exception anywhere. Every true strength is gained in struggle.

– Richard L. Evans